When the body dies, the brain survives in the nutrient solution: is it a life in the real or virtual world?
Updated on: 10-0-0 0:0:0

At the intersection of technology and philosophy, there is a thought-provoking thought experiment - "brain in a jar". This scenario asks if a person's body is dead, but the brain is retained in a nutrient solution and maintains function, can the brain still perceive a virtual world? Although this question stems from scientific hypotheses, the philosophical implications behind it go far beyond the boundaries of science.

"Brain in a Vat" challenges our understanding of the nature of life, consciousness, and reality. It is not only a scientific exploration of possibilities, but also a philosophical reflection on the way of human existence and the limits of cognition. This kind of thinking can be traced back to Descartes, the representative of Western skepticism. His idea of "I think, therefore I am" reveals the certainty of thinking itself, and the "brain in a vat" is a modern extension of this philosophical reflection that forces us to re-examine what the essence of a person is.

In numerous works of science fiction, virtual worlds are a recurring theme. From the matrix in The Matrix to the body swap in Alita: Battle Angel to the digital soul in Sword Art Online, these intricately constructed virtual worlds are not just a feast for the eyes, but also a profound exploration of human existence.

The virtual worlds in these works, although they are all different, have one thing in common: if a person's brain can connect with a perfect virtual world, is his life, emotions, and even self-identity real?

This makes us wonder if the so-called real world could just be a virtual world designed by higher-dimensional creatures. In this kind of thinking, the concept of "brain in a vat" reveals its philosophical connotation—it is not only a scientific hypothesis, but also a philosophical exploration of reality and perception, existence and nothingness.

The senses are the bridge between us and the world, and through the senses of sight, hearing, touch, etc., we perceive and recognize the world. However, under the experimental setting of "brain in a vat", if a person's senses are deprived, and only the brain is left to receive virtual signals in the nutrient solution, can his cognition still touch the truth?

Descartes' skepticism gives us a way to think. He suspects that all perception can be unreal, and that only thinking itself is certain. However, in the absence of feedback from the outside world, can you discern the truth from the false on your own? In the absence of sensory experience, can the virtual signals received by the brain be mistaken for reality?

Or, conversely, even with a real sensory experience, can we be sure that the world in front of us is not an elaborate illusion? These questions challenge our perceptions of truth and falsehood, and force us to re-examine the role of the senses in cognitive authenticity.

External information feedback plays a decisive role in the formation of people's cognition and self-awareness. A person's sense of self is not only based on internal thinking, but also needs to be constantly updated and confirmed through interaction with the external world. Our memories, emotions, and identities are all constructed through communication with others and society, as well as our perception of the physical environment.

In this process, the formation and maintenance of self-consciousness is particularly complex. If we compare self-awareness to an edifice, then external feedback is its solid cornerstone.

Without this feedback, self-consciousness may be like rootless water that cannot be condensed and formed. Therefore, even if the "brain in a vat" can experience various sensory stimuli through virtual signals, if there is no real external feedback, then this self-awareness can only be ethereal and unsustainable.

The essence of virtual signals is information, and this information simulates sensory experiences and creates an immersive feeling in the human brain. But in the context of the "brain in a vat", can the virtual signal constitute real cognition? According to the theory of cognitive dimensions, the boundary between the real and the virtual is not absolute. Cognition in the lower dimensions may not be able to comprehend the reality in the higher dimensions, and conversely, the reality in the higher dimensions may be illusory in the eyes of the lower dimensions.

This means that, for the "brain in a vat", the world built by the virtual signal is cognitively real.

If the brain cannot "see" the wider world beyond the current cognitive dimension, then this virtual world is all real to him. This relativistic cognitive theory provides a new perspective for us to understand the "brain in a vat", where the real and the virtual are no longer absolute opposites, but relative concepts closely related to the cognitive dimension.

Based on the above analysis, we can conclude that the experience of the "brain in a vat" is real in the process of receiving virtual signals and constructing a cognitive world. However, this reality is limited to the cognitive dimension of the brain.

If this boundary cannot be crossed, then the experience of this brain may be false to the outside world. This leads to a deeper question: What is the essence of life? How should we define our perception of the virtual world? These questions are worth exploring and pondering.